Saturday, July 28, 2007

Truth, Contemporary Philosophy, and the Postmodern Turn

J. P. Moreland

It is difficult to think of a topic of greater concern than the nature of truth. Indeed, truth and the knowledge thereof are the very rails upon which people ought to live their lives. And over the centuries, the classic correspondence theory of truth has outlived most of its critics. But these are postmodern times, or so we are often told, and the classic model, once ensconced deeply in the Western psyche, must now be replaced by a neo-pragmatist or some other anti-realist model of truth, at least for those concerned with the rampant victimization raging all around us. Thus, "We hold these truths to be self evident" now reads "Our socially constructed selves arbitrarily agree that certain chunks of language are to be esteemed in our linguistic community." Something has gone wrong here, and paraphrasing the words of Mad magazine’s Alfred E. Newman, "We came, we saw, and we conked out!"
The astute listener will have already picked up that I am an unrepentant correspondence advocate who eschews the various anti-realist views of truth. In what follows I shall weigh in on the topic first, by sketching out the correspondence theory and the postmodern rejection of it, and second, by identifying five confusions of which I believe postmodern revisionists are guilty. I shall close by warning that not only are postmodern views of truth and knowledge confused, but postmodernism is an immoral and cowardly viewpoint such that persons who love truth and knowledge, especially disciples of the Lord Jesus, should do everything they can to heal the plague that postmodernism has and inevitably does leave.

What is the Correspondence Theory of Truth?
In its simplest form, the correspondence theory of truth says that a proposition is true just in case it corresponds to reality, when what it asserts to be the case is the case. More generally, truth obtains when a truth bearer stands in an appropriate correspondence relation to a truth maker:
truth bearer -------> correspondence relation --------> truth maker
Certain clarifications are called for. First, what is the truth bearer? The thing that is either true or false is not a sentence, statement or other piece of language, but a proposition. A proposition is, minimally, the content of a sentence. For example, "It is raining" and "Es regnet" are two different sentences that express the same proposition. A sentence is a linguistic object consisting in a sense perceptible string of markings formed according to a culturally arbitrary set of syntactical rules, a grammatically well-formed string of spoken or written scratchings/sounds. Sentences are true just in case they express a true proposition or content. We will return to the topic of propositions later.
What about truth-makers? What is it that makes a proposition true? The best answer is facts. A fact is some real, that is, obtaining state of affairs in the world, for example, grass’s being green, an electron’s having negative charge, God’s being all-loving. For present purposes, this identification of the truth-maker will do, but the account would need to be filled out to incorporate future states of affairs that will obtain or counterfactual states of affairs that would have obtained given such and such.
Returning to present purposes, consider the proposition that grass is green. This proposition is true just in case a specific fact, viz., grass's being green, actually obtains in the real world. If Sally has the thought that grass is green, the specific state of affairs, (grass actually being green) "makes" the propositional content of her thought true just in case the state of affairs actually is the way the proposition represents it to be.
Grass’s being green makes Sally’s thought true even if Sally is blind and cannot tell whether or not it is true, and even if Sally does not believe the thought. Reality makes thoughts true or false. A thought is not made true by someone believing it or by someone being able to determine whether or not it is true. Put differently, evidence allows one to tell whether or not a thought is true, but the relevant fact is what makes it true. It goes without saying that "makes" in "a fact makes a proposition true" is not causal, but rather, is a substitution instance of "in virtue of"the proposition is true in virtue of the fact.
Our study of truth bearers has already taken us into the topic of the correspondence relation. Correspondence is a two-placed relation between a proposition and a relevant fact that is its intentional object. A two-placed relation, such as "larger than", is one that requires two things (say, a desk and a book) before it holds. Similarly, the truth relation of correspondence holds between two things a relevant fact and a proposition just in case the fact matches, conforms to, corresponds with the proposition.

Why Believe the Correspondence Theory?
What reasons can be given for accepting the correspondence theory of truth? Many are available, but the simplest is the descriptive argument. The descriptive argument focuses on a careful description and presentation of specific cases of coming to experience truth to see what can be learned from them about truth itself. As an example, consider the case of Joe and Frank. While in his office, Joe receives a call from the university bookstore that a specific book he had ordered Richard Swinburne's The Evolution of the Soul has arrived and is waiting for him. At this point, a new mental state occurs in Joe's mind the thought that Swinburne's The Evolution of the Soul is in the bookstore.
Now Joe, being aware of the content of the thought, becomes aware of two things closely related to it: the nature of the thought's intentional object (Swinburne's book being in the bookstore) and certain verification steps that would help him to determine the truth of the thought. For example, he knows that it would be irrelevant for verifying the thought to go swimming in the Pacific Ocean. Rather, he knows that he must take a series of steps that will bring him to a specific building and look in certain places for Swinburne's book in the university bookstore.
So Joe starts out for the bookstore, all the while being guided by the proposition that Swinburne's The Evolution of the Soul is in the bookstore. Along the way, his friend Frank joins him, though Joe does not tell Frank where he is going or why. They arrive at the store and both see Swinburne's book there. At that moment, Joe and Frank simultaneously have a certain sensory experience of seeing Swinburne's book The Evolution of the Soul. But Joe has a second experience not possessed by Frank. Joe experiences that his thought matches, corresponds with an actual state of affairs. He is able to compare his thought with its intentional object and "see," be directly aware of, the truth of the thought. In this case, Joe actually experiences the correspondence relation itself and truth itself becomes an object of his awareness. "Truth" is ostensively defined by this relation Joe experiences.

Postmodernism and Truth
Postmodernism is a loose coalition of diverse thinkers from several different academic disciplines, so it is difficult to characterize postmodernism in a way that would be fair to this diversity. Still, it is possible to provide a fairly accurate characterization of postmodernism in general, since it friends and foes understand it well enough to debate its strengths and weaknesses.
As a philosophical standpoint, postmodernism is primarily a reinterpretation of what knowledge is and what counts as knowledge. More broadly, it represents a form of cultural relativism about such things as reality, truth, reason, value, linguistic meaning, the self and other notions. On a postmodernist view, there is no such thing as objective reality, truth, value, reason and so forth. All these are social constructions, creations of linguistic practices and, as such, are relative not to individuals, but to social groups that share a narrative.
Postmodernism denies the correspondence theory, claiming that truth is simply a contingent creation of language which expresses customs, emotions, and values embedded in a community’s linguistic practices. For the postmodernist, if one claims to have the truth in the correspondence sense, this assertion is a power move that victimizes those judged not to have the truth.

Five Confusions that Plague Postmodernism
According to Brian McLaren, making absolute truth claims becomes problematic in the postmodern context. Says McLaren, "I think that most Christians grossly misunderstand the philosophical baggage associated with terms like absolute or objective (linked to foundationalism and the myth of neutrality)….Similarly, arguments that pit absolutism versus relativism, and objectivism versus subjectivism, prove meaningless or absurd to postmodern people…" McLaren not only correctly identifies some central postmodern confusions, but his statement indicates he exhibits some of the confusions himself. Let’s try to unpack some of the philosophical baggage to which McLaren refers and bring come clarity to the confusion.
#1 Metaphysical vs. epistemic notions of absolute truth
The first postmodern confusion involves metaphysical vs. epistemic notions of absolute truth. In the metaphysical and correct sense, absolute truth is the same thing as objective truth. On this view, people discover truth, they do not create it, and a claim is made true or false in some way or another by reality itself, totally independently of whether the claim is accepted by anyone. Moreover, an absolute truth conforms to the three fundamental laws of logic, which are themselves absolute truths. According to objectivism, a commitment to the absolute truth of some proposition P entails no thesis about a knowing subject’s epistemic situation regarding P.
By contrast with the metaphysical notion, postmodernists claim that a commitment to absolute truth is rooted in Cartesian anxiety and its need for absolute certainty and, accordingly, claim that acceptance of the absolute truth of P entails acceptance of the conjunction of P’s truth in the objective sense and the possibility of a (finite) knowing subject having Cartesian certainty with respect to P. Thus, one postmodernist recently opined that commitment to objective truth and the correspondence theory is merely "…an epistemic project [that] is funded by Cartesian anxiety,’ a product of methodological doubt…"
As I have already pointed out, this claim is entirely false philosophically. Advocates of a correspondence theory of objective truth take the view to be a realist metaphysical thesis and they steadfastly reject all attempts to epistemologize the view. Moreover, historically, it is incredible to assert that the great Western thinkers from Aristotle up to Descartes correspondence advocates all had any concern whatever about truth and Cartesian anxiety. The great correspondence advocate Aristotle was hardly in a Cartesian quandary when he wisely pointed out that in the search for truth, one ought not expect a greater degree of epistemic strength than is appropriate to the subject matter, a degree of strength that varies from topic to topic. The correspondence theory was not born when Descartes came out of his stove, and postmodernists lose credibility when they pretend otherwise.
#2 Two confusions about epistemic objectivity
Postmodernists also reject the notion that rationality is objective on the grounds that no one approaches life in a totally objective way without bias. Thus, objectivity is impossible, and observations, beliefs and entire narratives are theory-laden. There is no neutral standpoint from which to approach the world. Therefore, observations, beliefs and so forth are perspectival constructions that reflect the viewpoint implicit in one's own web of beliefs. For example, Stanley Grenz claims that postmodernism rejects the alleged modernist view of reason which "…entails a claim to dispassionate knowledge, a person’s ability to view reality not as a conditioned participant but as an unconditioned observer to peer at the world from a vantage point outside the flux of history."
Regarding knowledge, postmodernists believe that there is no point of view from which one can define knowledge itself without begging the question in favor of one's own view. "Knowledge" is a construction of one's social, linguistic structures, not a justified, truthful representation of reality by one's mental states. For example, knowledge amounts to what is deemed to be appropriate according to the professional certification practices of various professional associations. As such, knowledge is a construction that expresses the social, linguistic structures of those associations, nothing more, nothingless.less.
These postmodernist claims represent some very deep confusions about the notion of objectivity. As a first step towards clearing away this confusion, we need to draw a distinction between psychological and rational objectivity. It is clear from the quote above that Grenz’ confused understanding of objectivity is at least partly rooted in his mistaken conflation of these two senses. Psychological objectivity is detachment, the absence of bias, a lack of commitment either way on a topic.
Do people ever have psychological objectivity? Yes, they do, typically, in areas in which they have no interest or about which they know little or nothing. Note carefully two things about psychological objectivity. For one thing, it is not necessarily a virtue. It is if one has not thought deeply about an issue and has no convictions regarding it. But as one develops thoughtful, intelligent convictions about a topic, it would be wrong to remain "unbiased", that it, uncommitted regarding it. Otherwise, what role would study and evidence play in the development of a one's approach to life? Should one remain "unbiased" that cancer is a disease, that rape is wrong, that the New Testament was written in the first century, that there is design in the universe, if one has discovered good reasons for each believe? No, one should not.
For another thing, while it is possible to be psychologically objective in some cases, most people are not psychologically objective regarding the vast majority of the things they believe. In these cases, it is crucial to observe that a lack of psychological objectivity does not matter, nor does it cut one off from knowing or seeing the world directly the way it is, or from presenting and arguing for one's convictions. Why? Because a lack of psychological objectivity does not imply a lack of rational objectivity and it is the latter than matters most, not the former.
To understand this, we need to get clear on the notion of rational objectivity. Rational objectivity is the state of having accurate epistemic access to the thing itself. This entails that if one has rational objectivity regarding some topic, then one can discern the difference between genuinely good and bad reasons/evidence for a belief about that topic and one can hold the belief for genuinely good reasons/evidence. The important thing here is that bias does not stand between a knowing subject and an intentional object nor does it eliminate a person's ability to assess the reasons for something. Bias may make it more difficult, but not impossible. If bias made rational objectivity impossible, then no teacher including the postmodernist herself could responsibly teach any view the teacher believed on any subject! Nor could the teacher teach opposing viewpoints, because she would be biased against them!
We will return below to the topic of cognitive access to the objects of consciousness, but for now I simply note that Grenz exhibits the twin confusions, so common among postmodernists, of failing to assess properly the nature and value of psychological objectivity, and of failing to distinguish and properly assess the relationship between psychological and rational objectivity.
#3 Confusions between classical foundationalism and foundationalism per se
Postmodernists reject foundationalism as a theory of epistemic justification. For example, as they assert "the demise of foundationalism," Stanley Grenz and John Franke observe with irony, "How infirm the foundation." Rodney Clapp claims that foundationalism has been in "dire straits" for some time, avowing that "few if any careful thinkers actually rely on foundationalist thinking," even though they cling like addicted smokers to "foundationalist rhetoric." Says Clapp, evangelicals "should be nonfoundationalists exactly because we are evangelicals." Nancey Murphy is concerned to justify a "postmodern" theological method in the face of "a general skeptical reaction to the demise of foundationalism in epistemology."
A major reason for this rejection is the idea that foundationalism represents a quest for epistemic certainty and it is this desire to have certainty that provides the intellectual impetus for foundationalism. This so-called Cartesian anxiety is alleged to be the root of foundationalist theories of epistemic justification. But, the argument continues, there is no such certainty and the quest for it is an impossible one. Further, that quest is misguided because people do not need certainty to live their lives well. Sometimes Christian postmodernists support this claim by asserting that the quest for certainty is at odds with biblical teaching about faith, the sinfulness of our intellectual and sensory faculties, and the impossibility of grasping an infinite God.
Unfortunately, this depiction of the intellectual motives for foundationalism represents a confusion between foundationalism per se and an especially extreme Cartesian form of foundationalism, with the result that versions of modest foundationalism are simply not taken into consideration. To see this, note that "foundationalism" refers to a family of theories about what kinds of grounds constitute justification for belief, all of which hold the following theses:
1. A proper noetic structure is foundational, composed of properly basic beliefs and non-basic beliefs, where non-basic beliefs are based either directly or indirectly on properly basic beliefs, and properly basic beliefs are non-doxastically grounded, that is, not based entirely on other beliefs;
2. The basing relation which confers justification is irreflexive and asymmetrical; and
3. A properly basic belief is a belief which meets some Condition C, where the choice of C marks different versions of foundationalism.
Classical foundationalism, of which the Cartesian project is the paradigm example, holds that Condition C is indubitability (or some relevantly similar surrogate): the ground of the belief must guarantee the truth of the belief. It is recognized in nearly all quarters that classical foundationalism is too ambitious. Even granting, as I certainly would, that there are some indubitable beliefs, there simply aren’t enough of them to ground our entire noetic structure. Further, it clearly seems that certain beliefs which are not indubitable may legitimately be held as properly basic, for example, beliefs grounded in perception, memory, or testimony. And more: classical foundationalism is motivated largely by the belief that certainty is a necessary condition of knowledge, or that one must know that one knows in order to have knowledge. But these analyses are either too strict or lead to an infinite regress, leading in either case to the skeptic’s lair.
In point of fact, the past three decades have witnessed the development of various versions of foundationalism that avoid the criticisms leveled against the classical version. Among contemporary epistemologists, modest foundationalism of some form is, as one philosopher put it, the "dominant position." Thus, it is intellectually irresponsible for Clapp, Murphey and others to claim that foundationalism is losing favor among philosophers. As far as I can tell, apart from intellectual dishonesty, this false viewpoint can be sustained only by conflating classical foundationalism with foundationalism per se, but this is simply mistaken as the widespread acceptance of modest foundationalism makes clear. Modest foundationalism holds that Condition C is something weaker than indubitability: the ground of the belief must be truth-conducive. Thus at least some properly basic beliefs in a modest foundationalism are defeasible (subject to being shown to be false by subsequent evidence).#4 Confusions about the identity of the truth bearer
As we have already seen, the informed correspondence theorist will say that propositions are truth bearers. What is a proposition? Minimally, it is the content of declarative sentences/statements and thoughts/beliefs that is true or false. Beyond that philosophers are in disagreement, but most would agree that a proposition 1) is not located in space or time; 2) is not identical to the linguistic entities that may be used to express it; 3) is not sense perceptible; 4) is such that the same proposition may be in more then one mind at once; 5) need not be grasped by any (at least finite) person to exist and be what it is; 6) may itself be an object of thought when, for example, one is thinking about the content of one's own thought processes; 7) is in no sense a physical entity.
By contrast, a sentence is a linguistic type or token consisting in a sense perceptible string of markings formed according to a culturally arbitrary set of syntactical rules. A statement is a sequence of sounds or body movements employed by a speaker to assert a sentence on a specific occasion. So understood, neither sentences nor statements are good candidates for the basic truth bearer.
It is pretty easy to show that having or using a sentence (or any other piece of language) is neither necessary nor sufficient for thinking or having propositional content. First it’s not necessary. Children think prior to their acquisition of language how else could they thoughtfully learn language and, indeed, we all think without language regularly. Moreover, the same propositional content may be expressed by a potentially infinite number of pieces of language and, thus, that content is not identical to any linguistic entity. This alone does not show that language is not necessary for having propositional content. But when one attends to the content that is being held constant as arbitrary linguistic expressions are selected to express it, that content may easily be seen to satisfy the non-linguistic traits of a proposition listed above.
Second, it’s not sufficient. If erosion carved an author less linguistic scribble in a hillside, for example, "I’m eroding", then strictly speaking it would have no meaning or content, though it would be empirically equivalent to another token of this type that would express a proposition were it the result of authorial intent.
Postmodernists attack a straw man when they focus on the alleged inadequacies of linguistic objects to do the work required of them in a correspondence theory of truth. Speaking for himself and other postmodernists, Joseph Natoli claims that "No one representation, or narrative, can reliably represent the world because language/pictures/sounds (signifiers) are not permanent labels attached to the things of the world nor do the things of the world dwell inside such signifiers." Unfortunately, even granting the fact that language (and certain sensations) is problematic if taken to represent things in the world (e.g., that the language/world hookup is arbitrary), it follows that human subjects cannot accurately represent the world only if we grant the further erroneous claim that representational entities are limited to language (and certain sensations). But this is precisely what the sophisticated correspondence theorist denies.
Again, Richard Rorty says "To say that truth is not our there is simply to say that where there are no sentences there is not truth, that sentences are elements of human language, and that human languages are human creations. Truth cannot be out there cannot exist independently of the human mind because sentences cannot so exist, or be out there….Only descriptions…can be true and false." It should be obvious that Rorty attacks a straw man and that his argument goes through only if we grant that sentences are the fundamental truth bearers.#5 Confusions about perception and intentionality
Postmodernists adopt a highly contentious model of perception and intentionality, often without argument, and they seem to enjoin serious consideration of a prima facie more plausible model. The result is that postmodernists are far too pessimistic about the prospects of human epistemic success.
Postmodernists adopt a linguistic version of Rene Descartes’ idea theory of perception (and intentionality generally). To understand the idea theory, and the postmodern adaptation of it, a good place to start is with a common sense, critical realist view of perception. According to critical realism, when a subject is looking at a red object such as an apple, the object itself is the direct object of the sensory state. What one sees directly is the apple itself. True, one must have a sensation of red to apprehend the apple, but on the critical realist view, the sensation of red is to be understood as a case of being-appeared-to-redly and analyzed as a self-presenting property. What is a self-presenting property? If some property F is a self-presenting one, then it is by means of F that a relevant external object is presented directly to a person, and F presents itself directly to the person as well. Thus, F presents its object mediately though directly, and itself immediately.
This is not as hard to understand as it first may appear. Sensations, such as being-appeared-to-redly, are an important class of self-presenting properties. If Jones is having a sensation of red while looking at an apple, then having the property of being-appeared-to-redly as part of his consciousness modifies his substantial self. When Jones has this sensation, it is a tool that presents the red apple mediately to him and the sensation also presents itself to Jones. What does it mean to say that the sensation presents the apple to him mediately? Simply this: it is in virtue of or by means of the sensation that Jones directly sees the apple itself.
Moreover, by having the sensation of red, Jones is directly aware both of the apple and his own awareness of the apple. For the critical realist, the sensation of red may, indeed, be a tool or means that Jones uses to become aware of the apple, but he is thereby directly aware of the apple. His awareness of the apple is direct in that nothing stands between Jones and the apple, not even his sensation of the apple. That sensation presents the apple directly, though as a tool, Jones must have the sensation as a necessary condition for seeing the apple. On the critical realist view, a knowing subject is not trapped behind or within anything, including a viewpoint, a narrative, an historical-linguistic perspective. To have an entity in the external world as an object of intentionality is to already be "out there"; there is no need to escape anything. One is not trapped behind one’s eyeballs or anything else. It is a basic fallacy of logic to infer that one sees a point-of-viewed-object from the fact that one sees an object from a point of view.
Before leaving the critical realist view, it is important to say that the theory does not limit self-presenting properties to those associated with the five senses and, therefore, does not limit the objects of direct awareness to ordinary sensory objects. The critical realist will say that a knowing subject is capable of direct acquaintance with a host of non-sense-perceptible objects one's’s own ego and its mental states, various abstract objects like the laws of mathematics or logic, and spirit beings, including God.
By contrast, for Descartes’ idea theory, one’s ideas, in this case, sensations, stand between the subject and the object of perception. Jones is directly aware of his own sensation of the apple and indirectly aware of the apple in the sense that it is what causes the sensation to happen. On the idea theory, a perceiving subject is trapped behind his own sensations and cannot get outside them to the external world in order to compare his sensations to their objects to see if those sensations are accurate.
Now, in a certain sense, postmodernists believe that people are trapped behind something in the attempt to get to the external world. However, for them the wall between people and reality is not composed of sensations as it was for Descartes; rather, it is constituted by one’s community and its linguistic categories and practices. One’s language serves as a sort of distorting and, indeed, creative filter. One cannot get outside one’s language to see if one’s talk about the world is the way the world is. Thus, Grenz advocates a new outlook, allegedly representing some sort of consensus in the human sciences, that expresses "a more profound understanding of epistemology. Recent thinking has helped us see that the process of knowing, and to some extent even the process of experiencing the world, can occur only within a conceptual framework, a framework mediated by the social community in which we participate."
It has been noted repeatedly that such assertions are self-refuting. For if we are all trapped behind a framework such that simple, direct seeing is impossible, then no amount of recent thinking can help us see anything; all it could do would be to invite us to see something as such and such from within a conceptual framework. Given the self refuting nature of such claims, and given the fact that we all experience regularly the activity of comparing our conceptions of an entity with the entity itself as a way of adjusting those conceptions, it is hard to see why anyone, especially a Christian, would adopt the postmodern view. In any case, I have seldom seen the realist perspective seriously considered by postmodern thinkers, and until it is, statements like Grenz’ will be taken as mere mantras by many of us.

Final Remarks about the Immoral Nature of Postmodernism
For some time I have been convinced that postmodernism is rooted in pervasive confusions, and I have tried to point out what some of these are. I am also convinced that postmodernism is an irresponsible, cowardly abrogation of the duties that constitute a disciple’s calling to be a Christian intellectual and teacher.
In her provocative book entitled Longing to Know, Ester Meek asserts that humans as knowers exercise a profound responsibility to submit to the authoritative dictates of reality. Thus, "It is not responsible to deny objective truth and reality in knowing; it is irresponsible. It is not responsible to make the human knower or community of knowers the arbiters of a private truth and reality; it is irresponsible." Again, Meek claims that "Good, responsible knowing brings blessing, shalom; irresponsible knowing brings curse." In another place Meek warns that "…the kind of freedom implied by the thought that we humans completely determine our reality leaves us with a gnawing sense of the relative insignificance of our choices. I think it leads not to total responsibility but to careless irresponsibility, both with regard to ourselves and with regard to other humans, not to mention to the world. And, paradoxically, it leads not to a deeper sense of [communal or individual] identity and dignity but to a disheartening lack of it."
We Evangelicals need to pay careful attention to Meek’s claims. As humans, we live and ought to live our lives not merely by truth, but by knowledge of truth. Knowledge of truth gives us confident trust and access to reality. Moreover, as those called to be teachers and scholars for the church and, indeed, for the unbelieving world, we are called not only to impart and defend truth, but to impart and defend knowledge of truth and, even more, to impart and defend knowledge of truth as knowledge of truth. This entails that we must impart and defend the notion that we do, in fact, have knowledge of important spiritual and ethical truths. Among other things, this gives confidence in truth and knowledge to those we serve. Thus, we are irresponsible not simply if we fail to achieve knowledge of reality; we are doubly irresponsible if we fail to impart to others knowledge as knowledge. The corrosive affects of postmodernism eat away at the fulfillment of these duties and responsibilities that constitute our calling from Almighty God.
Meek goes on to point out that the achieving of knowledge and the teaching of it as knowledge "...calls for courageous resolve. And this courageous resolve, when proven true, merits the deep admiration of others." The need for such courage is especially grave today as we labor in an intellectual milieu in which the worldviews of naturalism and postmodernism both entail that there is no non-empirical knowledge, especially no religious or ethical knowledge.
Faced with such opposition and the pressure it brings, postmodernism is a form of intellectual pacifism that, at the end of the day, recommends backgammon while the barbarians are at the gate. It is the easy, cowardly way out that removes the pressure to engage alternative conceptual schemes, to be different, to risk ridicule, to take a stand outside the gate. But it is precisely as disciples of Christ, even more, as officers in His army, that the pacifist way out is simply not an option. However comforting it may be, postmodernism is the cure that kills the patient, the military strategy that concedes defeat before the first shot is fired, the ideology that undermines its own claims to allegiance. And it is an immoral, coward’s way out that is not worthy of a movement born out of the martyrs’ blood.

About the Author
J. P. Moreland, Ph.D. is Professor of Philosophy at Biola University. He has authored or co-authored many books including Christianity and the Nature of Science, Scaling the Secular City, Does God Exist?, Immortality: The Other Side of Death and The Life and Death Debate: Moral Issues of Our Times. He is also co-editor of Christian Perspectives on Being Human. His work has appeared in a wide variety of journals, including Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, and The American Philosophical Quarterly.
Where Did "I" Go?:The Loss of the Self in Postmodern Times

Rick Wade

Introduction
Who are you, anyway? Do you have an identity? What constitutes your identity? Who your parents are? Where you were born? What you do for a living?
Christians will rightly locate their identity ultimately in the God who created us in His image. We are His creation made for His purposes and glory. But are we important as individuals before God? Are we just a small part of the mass of humanity? Or are we unique individual selves with some characteristics shared by all people but also with a set of characteristics unique to ourselves?
According to the mindset overtaking the Western world called postmodernism, you aren’t really a self at all. You have no unique identity that is identifiable from birth to death; there’s no real "you" which remains constant throughout all of life’s changes.
In this article I want to examine the postmodern view of human nature and consider a possible direction for a Christian response.

Postmodernism: The End of Modernism
What is postmodernism? It is generally acknowledged that postmodernism isn’t a philosophy as we typically think of philosophies. It isn’t a single, well thought out philosophical system which seeks to define and answer the big questions of life. Postmodernism is more of a report on the mindset of Western culture in the latter half of the twentieth century. Some call it a mood. We might say it is a report on the failures of modernism along with a hodgepodge of suggestions for a new direction of thought and life.
Modernism is the name given to a way of thinking born in the Enlightenment era. It was a very optimistic outlook buoyed up by the successes of the sciences which produced some truly wonderful technology. We could understand ourselves and our world, and working together we could fix what was broken in nature and in human life.
Unfortunately the chickens have come home to roost; we’ve discovered that our optimism was misguided. We obviously haven't fixed all our problems, and the more we learn, the more we realize how little we know. Reason hasn't lived up to its Enlightenment reputation.
Not only have we not been able to fix everything, the technology we do have has had some bad side effects. For example, the mobility which has resulted from modern transportation has removed us from stable communities which provided standards of conduct, protection, and a sense of continuity between one’s home, work, and other activities of life. Add to that the globalization of our lives which brings us into contact with people from many different backgrounds with many different beliefs and ways of life, and we can see why we struggle to maintain some continuity in our own lives. We feel ourselves becoming fractured as we run this way and that; and at each destination we encounter different sets of values and expectations. As theologian Anthony Thiselton says, the resulting "loss of stability, loss of stable identity, and loss of confidence in global norms or goals breed deep uncertainty, insecurity, and anxiety."{1} We no longer take our cues from tradition or from our own inner "gyroscope"--an internalized set of values which guides our lives. Rather we are "other-directed." We take our cues from other people who are supposedly "in the know" and can tell us what we are supposed to do and be in each different compartment of our lives. We find ourselves "eager to conform, yet always in some doubt as to what exactly it [is] that [we are] to conform to."{2} We are "at home everywhere and nowhere, capable of a superficial intimacy with and response to everyone."{3}
All this produces in us a sense of constantly being in flux. The debate over which was fundamental in our universe--change or stability--occupied the thought of Greek philosophers long before Christ. This debate continues in our day. In fact, one writer noted that "postmodernism can be viewed as a debate about reality."{4} The search in modern times to find what is really real--what is true and stable--has given way. In postmodern times, change is fundamental; flux is normal.
In all of this we seem to lose our sense of identity. In fact, as we will see, avant garde postmodern thinkers say we have no self at all.

Basic Issues: Truth, Language, and Power
I noted earlier that postmodernism is more a report on the failures of modernism than a philosophy itself. One of the key issues which divides the two eras is that of truth. Whereas modernism was quite optimistic about our ability to know truth not only about ourselves and our world but also about how to make life better, postmodernism says we can’t really know truth at all. To mention one way our lack of confidence in reason to get at truth shows itself, consider how often disputes are settled with name- calling or a resort to the ever ready "Well, that's your opinion," as if that settles the issue, or even to force. As one scholar noted, "Argument becomes transposed into rhetoric. Rhetoric then comes to rely on force, seduction, or manipulation."{5}
Since we can’t really know truth¾if there is truth to be known¾we can't answer questions about ultimate reality. There is no one "story," as it's called, which explains everything. So, for example, the message of the Bible cannot be taken as true because it purports to give final answers for the nature of God, man, and the world. In the jargon of postmodernism, it is a metanarrative, a story covering all stories. Any metanarrative is rejected out of hand. We simply can’t have that kind of knowledge according to postmodernists.{6}
One of the basic problems in knowing truth is the problem of language. Knowledge is mediated by language, but postmodernists believe that language can't adequately relate truth. Why? Because there is a disjunction between our words and the realities they purport to reflect. Words don't accurately represent objective reality, it is thought; they are just human conventions. But if language is what we use to convey ideas, and words don't accurately reflect objective reality, then we can't know objective reality. What we do with words is not to reflect reality, but rather to create it. This is called constructivism,{7} the power to construct reality with our words.
What this means for human nature in particular is that we can’t really make universal statements about human beings. We can't know if there is such a thing as human nature. Those who hold to constructivism say that there is no human nature per se; we are what we say we are.
There is a second problem with language. Postmodernists are very sensitive to what they call the will-to-power. People exercise power and control over others, and language is one tool used for doing so.{8} For instance, we define roles for people, we make claims about God and what He requires of us, and so forth. In doing so, we define expectations and limits. Thus, with our words we control people.
As a result of this idea about language and its power to control, postmodernists are almost by definition suspicious. What people say and even more so what they write is suspected of being a tool for control over others.
What does this mean for human nature? It means that if we try to define human nature, we are seen as attempting to exercise control over people. As one person said, to make a person a subject--a topic of study and analysis--is to subject that person; in other words, to put him in a box and define his limits.
Thus, human nature can’t be defined, so for all practical purposes there is no human nature. There is more, though. Not only is there no human nature generally, but there are no individual selves either.

Postmodernism and the Self
Let’s look more closely at the postmodern view of the self.
Writer Walter Truett Anderson gives four terms postmodernists use to speak of the self which address the issues of change and multiple identities. The first is multiphrenia. This refers to the many different voices in our culture telling us who we are and what we are. As Kenneth Gergen, a professor of psychology, says, "For everything that we 'know to be true' about ourselves, other voices within respond with doubt and even derision."{9} Our lives are multi-dimensional. The various relationships we have in our lives pull us in different directions. We play "such a variety of roles that the very concept of an 'authentic self' with knowable characteristics recedes from view."{10} And these roles needn’t overlap or be congruent in any significant way. As Anderson says, "In the postmodern world, you just don’t get to be a single and consistent somebody."{11}
The second term used is protean. The protean self is capable of changing constantly to suit the present circumstances. "It may include changing political opinions and sexual behavior, changing ideas and ways of expressing them, changing ways of organizing one’s life."{12} Some see this as the process of finding one's true self. But others see it as a manifestation of the idea that there is no true, stable self.{13}
Thirdly, Anderson speaks of the de-centered self. This term focuses on the belief that there is no self at all. The self is constantly redefined, constantly undergoing change. As one philosopher taught, "The subject is not the speaker of language but its creation."{14} Thus, there is no enduring "I". We are what we are described to be.
Anderson's fourth term is self-in-relation. This concept is often encountered in feminist studies. It simply means that we live our lives not as islands unto ourselves but in relation to people and to certain cultural contexts. To rightly understand ourselves we must understand the contexts of our lives.{15}
If we put these four terms together, we have the image of a person who has no center, but who is drawn in many directions and is constantly changing and being defined externally by the various relations he or she has with others. All these ideas clearly go in a different direction than that taken by modern society. It was formerly believed that our goal should be to achieve wholeness, to find the integrated self, to pull all the seemingly different parts of ourselves together into one cohesive whole. Postmodernism says no; that can't happen because we aren't by nature one cohesive self.
So there is no "I", no inner self to wrestle with all these different roles and determine which I will accept and which I won't and, ultimately, who I really am. How, then, do changes come about? Who decides what I am like or who I am? According to postmodern thought, we are shaped by outside forces. We are socially constructed.

The Socially Constructed Life
What does it mean to be socially constructed? It means simply that one's society's values, languages, arts, entertainment, all that we grow up surrounded by, define who we are. We do not have fixed identities which are separable from our surroundings and which remain the same even though certain characteristics and circumstances may change.
It was once believed that what we do externally reflects what we are on the inside. But if there is no "inside," we must rely on that which is outside to define us. We are products of external forces over which we have varying levels of control. The suspicious postmodernist sees us as having little control at all over the forces impinging upon us.
Thus, we are created from the outside in, rather than from the inside out. If in traditional societies one's status was determined by one's role, and in modern societies one's status was determined by achievement, in postmodern times one’s status is determined by fashion or style.{16} As styles change, we must change with them or be left with our identity in question. It's one thing to want to fit in with one's peers. It's another altogether to believe that one’s true identity is bound up with the fashions of the day. But that's life in the postmodern world.
Being bound up with the fashions of the day, however, means that there is no eternal context for our lives. We are "historically situated."{17} That means that our lives can only be understood in the context of the present historical moment. All that matters is now. What I was yesterday is irrelevant; what I will be tomorrow is open.
Let's sum up our discussion to this point. In postmodern times there is no confidence in our ability to know truth. There is no metanarrative which serves to define and give a context to everything. Change is fundamental, and changes come often and do not always form a coherent pattern. There is no real human nature, nor are there real selves; there is no real "me" that is identifiable throughout my life. Whatever I am, I am because I have been "created", so to speak, by outside forces. One of the most potent forces is language with its ability to define and control. My life is like a story or text which is being written and rewritten constantly. How I am defined is what I am. What I am today is means nothing for tomorrow. To empower myself, I must take charge of defining myself, of writing my own story my way, not letting others write it for me.
But for many postmodernists this isn't really an individual exercise at all. I am a part of a group, and I'm expected to remain a part of my group and be defined in keeping with my group. Furthermore, no one outside the group is permitted to participate in the defining process. So, for example, men have nothing to say to women about how they are to act or what roles they are to fill.

Results
The bottom line in all this is what you already know. Life in the postmodern world is one of instability. To quote Thiselton again, the losses of stability and identity and confidence "breed deep uncertainty, insecurity and anxiety. . . . [T]he postmodern self lives daily with fragmentation, indeterminacy, and intense distrust" of all claims to ultimate truth or universal moral standards. This results in defensiveness and "an increasing preoccupation with self-protection, self-interest, and desire for power and the recovery of control. The postmodern self is thus predisposed to assume a stance of readiness for conflict."{18} Our fragmentation, our lack of an internal "gyroscope" to give direction and balance, the pressures of external forces to conform, the lack of continuity in our lives, together work to strip us of a sense of who we are, or that we are a single somebody at all.
Some people might despair over this. But many believe we should embrace this rather than fight it. If we aren't happy with our own individual "story", we should rewrite it. We need to simply accept our inner multiplicity and devise a story that accounts for it. "If meaning is constructed in language," says one writer, we must learn to tell "better, richer, more spacious stories" about our lives.{19}
But if the forces surrounding us are so strong, how shall we stand against them? If we find ourselves resisting others who try to define us or set standards for us, indicating that we believe they're strong enough to have an influence over us, how are we ever going to be able to avoid being a pawn for those who are more powerful? How can we avoid get sucked up into "group- think", where we're always expected to toe the party line? What happens to our own individuality? Is there no place for our individual unique sets of gifts and abilities, needs and desires, loves and concerns?
Consider also the potential for loss for the individual in favor of the group. What if the group's standards or goals diminish the individuals in the group? Prof. Ed Veith has spoken of the similarities between this mentality and that of Fascism with its suppression of the individual in favor of the group. With or without realizing it, postmodernists aren't establishing a basis for empowering the oppressed, but are "resurrecting ways of thinking that gave us world war and the Holocaust."{20} Veith quotes writer David Hirsch who said, "Purveyors of postmodern ideologies must consider whether it is possible to diminish human beings in theory, without, at the same time, making individual human lives worthless in the real world."{21}

A Christian Response
Is there an answer in Christ for the fragmented, suspicious, "non-selves" of the postmodern world?
In this writer's opinion, it is simple common sense that we are individual selves with an identity which we carry throughout our years despite the various changes we experience. "I" can be held accountable for the things "I" did five years ago. The individual brought to the witness stand is believed to be the same "self" who witnessed the particular events in the past. The worker is promised a pension when she retires with the understanding that the retiree will be the same self as the one who worked for many years.{22} Furthermore, we know that we have a set of abilities, great or small, that are our own and that we can use for good or for ill. We naturally resent being molded in the image of other people and prevented from expressing our own true nature.
Does Christ have anything to say to the postmodern individual who can’t shake the common sense view that he is the same person today that he was yesterday? Or to the person who wants to affirm or regain her own identity and chart a course for life that she as an individual can experience and learn from and within which to develop as an individual self?
Indeed He does. The call of God in Christ is to individuals within the larger story of God's work in this world.{23} For one thing, having been created by Him we see ourselves as ones who can be addressed as Jeremiah was with the news that God knew him before he was born. It was the same Jeremiah being formed in his mother’s womb to whom God spoke as an adult (Jer. 1:5). Furthermore, in Christ we recognize ourselves as responsible individuals who must give an account for our actions without pointing the finger of blame at "society" (Rev. 20:12).
In Christ we can acknowledge that we are shaped to a great extent by our surroundings, and that we are historically situated to an extent. But we aren't trapped. Redemption "promises deliverance from all the cause-effect chains of forces which hold the self to its past."{24}
There is more. In Christ the suspicion which marks postmodern man who is ever on guard against being redefined and controlled by others dissolves into a love which gives itself to the interests of God and other men.{25} The will-to-power of postmodern man which is self-defeating gives way to the will-to-love which reaches out to build up rather than to control.{26} We can indeed find common ground with people of other groups. "The cross of Christ in principle shatters the boundaries and conflicts between Jew and Gentile, female and male, free person and slave" (Gal. 3:28).{27} Recognizing our relative historical situatedness should help us to understand the importance of the local church as the social context within which barriers are destroyed.{28} In Christ, then, we have love rather than conflict, service rather than power, trust rather than suspicion.{29}
In Christ we recognize that sometimes life seems chaotic, that there are places of darkness in which we feel overwhelmed by outside forces that don’t behave the way we think they should. Consider the experiences of Job and of the writer of Ecclesiastes. But we are called to "set our minds on things above" (Col. 3:2), to put our confidence in "the fear of the Lord" (Prov. 9:10; Job. 28:28; Eccl. 12:13) rather than give in to despair or try to find a solution in simply rewriting our story with our own set of preferred "realities."{30}
Thiselton emphasizes the importance of the resurrection for postmodern man. "The resurrection holds out the promise of hope from beyond the boundaries of the historical situatedness of the postmodern self in its predicament of constraint.".{31} In addition, "Promise beckons 'from ahead' to invite the postmodern self to discover a reconstituted identity." It "constitutes 'a sure and steadfast anchor' (Heb. 6:19) which re-centres the self. It bestows on the self an identity of worth and provides purposive meaning for the present." The work of Christ promises a restoration of the individual self which will "once again [come] to bear fully the image of God in Christ (Heb. 1:3; Gen. 1:26) as a self defined by giving and receiving, by loving and being loved unconditionally."{32} As Steven Sandage writes, "The core absolute in life is not change but faith in our unchanging God, the 'anchor of the soul' that reminds us we are strangers longing for a better country " (Heb. 6:19; 11:1-16).{33}
The message of hope is the one postmodern men and women need to hear. That message, delivered two millennia ago, still speaks today. "The word of our God stands forever" (Isa. 40:8). Some things never change.

Notes
1. Anthony Thiselton, Interpreting God and the Postmodern Self: On Meaning, Manipulation and Promise (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995), 130.
2. Walter Truett Anderson, The Future of the Self: Inventing the Postmodern Person (New York: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam, 1997), 26.
3. David Reisman, with Nathan Glazer and Reuel Denney, The Lonely Crowd: A Study of the Changing American Character (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1950), 26; quoted in Anderson, 26.
4. Steven J. Sandage, "Power, Knowledge, and the Hermeneutics of Selfhood: Postmodern Wisdom for Christian Therapists," Mars Hill Review 12 (Fall 1998): 66.
5. Thiselton, 13.
6. Gene Edward Veith, Postmodern Times: A Christian Guide to Contemporary Thought and Culture (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1994), 49. Note Lyotard's brief definition: "Simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern as incredulity toward metanarratives." Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans., Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), xxiv).
7.Ibid., 47-51.
8. For a Christian's recognition of this in his own life, cf. Sandage, 68-69.
9. Kenneth J. Gergen, The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life (New York: Basic Books, 1990), 228. Quoted in Anderson, 38.
10. Gergen quoted in Anderson, 38.
11. Anderson, 38.
12. Ibid., 41.
13. Ibid., 42.
14. Ibid., 42-43.
15. Ibid., 51-56.
16. Veith, 85.
17. Thiselton, 42, 148-150.
18. Ibid., 130-31.
19. Anderson, 56.
20. Veith, 80.
21. David H. Hirsch, The Deconstruction of Literature: Criticism After Auschwitz (Hanover, NH: Brown University Press, 1991), 165; quoted in Veith, 80.
22. Thiselton, 74.
23. I am greatly indebted to Thiselton for this portion of the discussion. See chaps. 23 and 24.
24. Thiselton, 155.
25. Ibid., 160.
26. Ibid., 161.
27. Ibid., 43.
28. Cf. Sandage, 72.
29. Thiselton, 43.
30. Sandage, 71-72.
31. Thiselton, 43.
32. Ibid., 163.
33. Sandage, 73.

Tuesday, July 17, 2007

Gereja dan Negara

Pendeta Dr. Jan H. Rapar, Th.D., Ph.D.

Makalah ini dipresentasikan pada Konsultasi Teologi Persekutuan Gereja-gereja se-Sulawesi Utara dan Sulawesi Tengah, yang di adakan di Luwuk, Sulawesi Tengah, 16-18 Juni 1993

1. PENDAHULUAN
Manusia adalah makhluk yang senantiasa mengajukan pertanyaan tentang apa saja, sehingga dapatlah dikatakan bahwa manusia adalah makhluk bertanya. Justru hal itulah yang membedakan manusia dari makhluk lainnya. Pertanyaanlah pula yang menyebabkan adanya penelitian yang telah mengembangkan berbagai ilmu pengetahuan dan filsafat.[1] Menurut Prof. Beerling, "Sartre, filsuf eksistensi Perancis ... malahan mengatakan, bahwa kesadaran pada manusia adalah bersifat bertanya yang sebenar-benarnya."[2] Lewat upaya menjawab pertanyaan-pertanyaannya itu manusia ingin mendapatkan kebenaran [aletheia].[3] Oleh karena itu semua realitas yang masih tidak begitu jelas baginya dijadikan persoalan [problemma].[4] Dengan demikian ia dapat mengajukan pertanyaan-pertanyaan dan sekaligus berupaya untuk menjawab pertanyaan-pertanyaan itu, demi mencapai aletheia, agar supaya problemma tidak tetap tinggal sebagai problemma.
Untuk membahas Hubungan Gereja-Negara, pertama-tama kita perlu menjawab serangkaian pertanyaan sebagai berikut: Apakah Negara itu? Apa tujuan dan fungsi negara? Apakah Gereja itu? Apa tujuan dan fungsi Gereja? Sesudah itu barulah kita membahas tentang Hubungan Gereja-Negara, lewat upaya menjawab pertanyaan-pertanyaan: Mengapa ada hubungan antara Negara dan Gereja itu? Dan bagaimanakah hubungan Gereja-Negara itu?

2. APAKAH NEGARA ITU?
2.1. Pengertian etimologis
Negara berasal dari kata nagar (Sanskerta) yang berarti kota. Kata nagar kompatibel dengan kata polis (Yunani) yang pada mulanya berarti kota namun kemudian berarti juga negara. Pada masa kini, penggunaan istilah negara dihubungkan dengan kata etat (Perancis), staat (Belanda dan Jerman), state (Inggeris), yang berasal dari bahasa Latin status civilis. Dalam hal itu pengertian negara lebih mengacu kepada negara in abstracto dan bukan mengacu kepada segi fisik, seperti: tempat, batas-batas, jumlah penduduk dan sebagainya. Dalam arti yang abstrak itulah negara dalam bahasa Yunani disebut politeia. Dalam arti itulah pula kata politeia digunakan oleh Plato sebagai judul dari salah satu bukunya. Aristoteles menggunakan kata politeia yang mengacu kepada bentuk negara konstitusional, tetapi juga sewaktu-waktu mengacu kepada negara selaku he koinonia politike (persekutuan hidup yang berbentuk negara).
2.2. Hakikat Negara
Apakah sebenarnya negara itu? Apa benar yang dikatakan oleh Louis XIV bahwa l'etat c'est moi - aku adalah negara? Bagi Plato, negara adalah persatuan dari orang-orang yang sadar bahwa keinginan dan kebutuhan mereka yang banyak hanya mungkin terpenuhi jika mereka bersatu dan bekerja sama.[5] Aristoteles mengatakan bahwa "... setiap negara adalah suatu asosiasi".[6] Negara sebagai suatu asosiasi adalah persekutuan hidup politis.[7] Menurut John Locke, negara adalah asosiasi dari manusia-manusia individual yang membuat suatu pactum unionis dan pactum subjectionis demi menjamin hak-hak kodrati yang mereka miliki sebelum perjanjian masyarakat dibuat.[8] Bagi Jean-Jacques Rousseau, negara adalah persekutuan dari individu-individu yang membuat pakta sosial, yang melaluinya ia memberi diri kepada semua (bukan kepada seseorang atau kepada orang-orang tertentu) tanpa kehilangan hak dan kebebasannya.[9]
Dari pandangan beberapa filsuf besar tersebut di atas, terlihat bahwa pada hakikatnya, negara adalah persekutuan dari orang-orang yang menyadari bahwa mereka memiliki berbagai kebutuhan yang hanya dapat terpenuhi jika mereka bekerja sama, dan oleh karena itu mereka bersatu/bersekutu dengan membuat perjanjian agar hak-hak kodrati termasuk kebebasan mereka tetap terjamin. Yang dapat bersekutu dan membuat perjanjian hanyalah orang-orang yang sederajat, sebab itu negara harus menjamin kesamaan derajat yang justru menjadi salah satu landasan bagi eksistensi negara. Secara implisit dapat dikatakan bahwa dalam kesamaan derajat itu telah terkandung pengertian tidak adanya pembedaan antara pemerintah dan yang diperintah, mayoritas dan minoritas, kaya dan miskin, dan sebagainya; dalam arti bahwa semua hak-hak kodrati dan kebebasan mereka harus dijamin oleh negara. Jika pemerintah dan yang diperintah sama derajat, sama hak dan kebebasan sehingga yang berbeda hanyalah fungsi mereka, maka itu berarti tidak dibenarkan pemerintah memerintah secara otoriter apalagi menjadi diktator. Jika setiap warga negara baik dari golongan yang mayoritas maupun yang minoritas sama derajat dan memiliki hak serta kebebasan yang sama, maka itu berarti bukan hanya tidak boleh ada diktator mayoritas atau pun tirani minoritas, tetapi juga tidak boleh ada sikap dan tindakan yang mengistimewakan sang mayoritas atau mengkhususkan sang minoritas. Dalam kesadaran akan perlunya kerja sama yang mempersatukan dan mempersekutukan manusia itu, terkandung pula pengertian akan adanya kewajiban masing-masing dalam persekutuan (negara) itu, demi mencapai tujuan bersama. Dengan demikian dalam kehidupan bernegara bukan hanya ada hak, tetapi juga ada kewajiban.

3. APAKAH TUJUAN NEGARA?
Pertanyaan itu telah diajukan sejak negara itu eksis, dan jawaban yang diberikan berbeda-beda dari abad ke abad. Kita mulai dengan pandangan ekstrim yang mengatakan bahwa tujuan negara ialah menjadikan negara itu berkuasa. Konon seorang menteri Kerajaan Tiongkok bernama Yang (abad ke 3 atau ke 2 SM) mengatakan bahwa jika rakyat lemah berarti negara kuat dan jika negara kuat berarti rakyat lemah oleh karena itu agar negara kuat maka rakyatnya harus dibuat lemah. Hal itu sejalan dengan gagasan Machiavelli yang mengatakan bahwa tujuan negara adalah negara itu sendiri. Oleh karena itu Machiavelli menegaskan bahwa "penguasa harus senantiasa mengupayakan kejayaan dan kemakmuran negara, sedangkan warga negara harus sedia mengorbankan apa saja demi negara."[10] Ajaran yang menekankan kepentingan negara di atas segala-galanya disebut totaliterisme. Praktek totaliterisme yang paling mencolok dalam sejarah politik terlihat lewat fasisme dan naziisme.
Jika negara bukanlah tujuan yang sesungguhnya dari negara, maka apakah sebenarnya tujuan negara itu? Pandangan Aristoteles mengenai tujuan negara tidak begitu berbeda dengan pandangan Plato yang berpendapat bahwa tujuan negara ialah untuk mencapai moralitas jiwa (soul's morality) atau keutamaan (excellence) bagi warganya. Aristoteles mengatakan bahwa tujuan negara ialah summum bonum (the highest good) bagi manusia.[11] John Locke mengatakan bahwa tujuan negara ialah memelihara hak-hak kodrati manusia.[12] Jacobsen dan Lipman mengatakan bahwa tujuan negara ialah menegakkan ketertiban, mempromosikan kesejahteraan individual, kesejahteraan umum dan moralitas.[13]
Menyimak dengan cermat pandangan para pemikir tersebut di atas maka dapatlah dikatakan bahwa tujuan negara adalah demi kebaikan manusia.[14] Jadi, jelas terlihat bahwa tujuan negara sebagai persekutuan hidup politis bukanlah untuk negara itu sendiri. Negara eksis bukanlah demi negara, melainkan demi manusia yang membentuk persekutuan hidup politis yang disebut negara. Dengan demikian, tujuan ultim negara adalah manusia. Hal itu pun terlihat pada tujuan negara Republik Indonesia, sebagaimana yang tercantum dalam UUD 1945, sebagai berikut: "... melindungi segenap bangsa Indonesia dan seluruh tumpah darah Indonesia dan untuk memajukan kesejahteraan umum, mencerdaskan kehidupan bangsa dan ikut melaksanakan ketertiban dunia yang berdasarkan kemerdekaan, perdamaian abadi dan keadilan sosial..."[15] Jelas terlihat bahwa tujuan ultim negara Republik Indonesia adalah summum bonum manusia Indonesia. Negara Republik Indonesia bukan eksis demi negara itu sendiri, melainkan demi martabat, keadilan, kesejahteraan umum, dan kemakmuran manusia pada umumnya, dan khususnya manusia Indonesia.

4. FUNGSI NEGARA
Ada berbagai teori tentang fungsi negara, mulai dari pandangan ekstrim kaum anarkis yang merasa tidak membutuhkan pemerintah dan peraturan, sampai dengan pandangan ekstrim komunisme yang menghendaki agar negara mengambil alih seluruh alat produksi dan distribusi di samping harus mengatur secara rinci dan mencampuri hampir seluruh kehidupan pribadi setiap warga negara.[16] Namun pada saat ini, kita tidak akan membicarakan seluruh teori yang pernah dicetuskan dan dipraktekkan, melainkan hanya beberapa pandangan penting yang dikenal dalam filsafat politik.
Aristoteles berpendapat bahwa sesuai dengan kodratnya, manusia adalah politikon zoon,[17] yang secara harfiah berarti hewan/makhluk hidup yang hidup bernegara. Makhluk hidup yang tidak hidup bernegara, jika ia bukan binatang, ia adalah dewa! Makhluk yang demikian itu, jika ia tidak di bawah manusia (subhuman), maka pastilah ia di atas manusia (superhuman).[18] Dengan demikian jelas terlihat bahwa menurut Aristoteles, manusia hanya memanusia jika ia hidup bernegara, karena yang tidak bernegara hanyalah makhluk hidup yang di bawah manusia atau yang di atas manusia. Apabila manusia hanya memanusia lewat negara, maka itu berarti bahwa fungsi negara yang terutama ialah memanusiakan manusia. Negara yang tidak berfungsi memanusiakan manusia, adalah negara yang bukan hanya mengingkari fungsinya, tetapi juga mengkhianati eksistensinya.
Fungsi memanusiakan manusia itu secara berangsur-angsur semakin dirinci oleh pemikir-pemikir politik dan pada masa kini, mereka yang menjunjung demokrasi mengatakan bahwa fungsi negara ialah melindungi kebebasan dan persamaan warganegara serta membuat konstitusi yang membatasi kekuasaan pemerintah, termasuk juga kesamaan individu (baik rakyat biasa maupun pemerintah) di hadapan hukum.[19] Mac Iver mengatakan bahwa ada tiga aspek intern dari fungsi negara, yaitu: ketertiban, perlindungan, pemeliharaan dan pengembangan.[20] Fungsi-fungsi itu mencakup seluruh segi kehidupan warga negara, seperti: aspek ekonomi, sosial, kultural, edukasi, spiritual dan sebagainya.
Apakah yang menjadi fungsi negara Republik Indonesia menurut paham demokrasi Pancasila? Jika tujuan negara sebagaimana yang tercantum dalam pembukaan UUD 1945 disimak dengan cermat maka se-sungguhnya ada empat pokok tujuan negara yang sekaligus merupakan tugas dan fungsi negara Republik Indonesia, yaitu:
1 melindungi segenap bangsa Indonesia dan seluruh tumpah darah Indonesia
2 memajukan kesejahteraan umum
3 mencerdaskan kehidupan bangsa
4 ikut melaksanakan ketertiban dunia yang berdasarkan kemerdekaan, kebangsaan, perdamaian abadi dan keadilan sosial.
Demi mencapai tujuan negara itu, maka negara Republik Indonesia harus berfungsi sebaik-baiknya untuk melindungi, memajukan ke-sejateraan umum, mencerdaskan kehidupan bangsa, dan ikut melak-sanakan ketertiban dunia dalam rangka memampukan manusia menyambut dan mewujudnyatakan kemanusiaan manusia dalam proses pembangunan manusia secara integral.

5. KEKUASAAN NEGARA
Dilihat dari aspek hukum tatanegara, maka sesungguhnya negara itu merupakan suatu organisasi kekuasaan. Kekuasaan adalah sarana yang sangat penting bagi negara untuk mencapai tujuan negara dan agar negara dapat berfungsi dengan sebaik-baiknya. Berbicara mengenai kekuasaan, biasanya ada tiga hal yang sering dibahas dalam filsafat politik, yaitu:
1 sumber kekuasaan
2 pemegang kekuasaan, dan
3 penyelenggaraan kekuasaan.
Mengenai sumber kekuasaan, biasanya ada dua jawaban yang diberikan. Pertama, jawaban dari teori teokrasi mengatakan bahwa negara memperoleh kekuasaan dari Tuhan. Pemikir-pemikir seperti Augustinus, Thomas Aquinas, Marsilius dan lain-lain, sependapat bahwa sumber kekuasaan negara adalah Tuhan. Kedua, jawaban dari teori hukum alam mengatakan bahwa negara memperoleh kekuasaan itu dari rakyat. Bagi Rousseau, masing-masing individu menyerahkan kekuasaan kepada masyarakat, lalu kemudian lewat perjanjian masyarakat, kekuasaan itu diserahkan kepada raja/negara. Thomas Hobbes berpendapat bahwa kekuasaan itu langsung diserahkan oleh masing-masing individu kepada raja. Kendatipun ada perbedaan pendapat mengenai penyerahan kekuasaan itu, namun semua penganut teori hukum alam sependapat bahwa kekuasaan itu berasal dari rakyat.
Terlepas apakah kekuasaan negara itu berasal dari Tuhan atau berasal dari rakyat, yang pasti ialah bahwa kekuasaan itu tidak independen dan tidak memiliki kedaulatan di dalam dirinya sendiri. Oleh karena itu kekuasaan harus dipertanggungjawabkan kepada si pemberi kekuasaan.
Mengenai pemegang kekuasaan tertinggi dalam negara yang dalam teori politik disebut juga dengan kedaulatan, ada lima teori yang dikenal, yaitu:
1 teori kedaulatan Tuhan, mengatakan bahwa kekuasaan tertinggi berada pada Tuhan
2 teori kedaulatan raja mengajarkan bahwa kekuasaan tertinggi berada pada raja yang kemudian diwariskannya secara turun-temurun
3 teori kedaulatan rakyat mengatakan bahwa kekuasaan tertinggi berada pada rakyat, karena negara dan pemerintahan adalah dari, oleh dan untuk rakyat
4 teori kedaulatan negara mengajarkan bahwa negaralah yang memiliki kedaulatan tertinggi, karena yang menciptakan hukum dan yang membuat undang-undang adalah negara, dan
5 teori kedaulatan hukum mengajarkan bahwa hukumlah yang merupakan kekuasaan yang tertinggi dalam negara, karena baik raja/penguasa negara, maupun rakyat/warga negara, bahkan negara itu sendiri, tunduk kepada hukum.
Mengenai penyelenggaraan kekuasaan, menurut Plato harus dilakukan secara persuasif, bagaikan seorang ayah terhadap anak-anaknya yang tidak memaksa dan tidak menggunakan kekerasan.[21] Aristoteles mengatakan bahwa penyelenggaraan kekuasaan negara haruslah seperti suami terhadap istrinya yang menghargai dan menghormati kebebasan dan kedewasaan istrinya itu.[22] Pada masa kini telah dikembangkan penyelenggaraan kekuasaan negara secara partisipatif yang dikenal juga dengan penyelenggaraan kekuasaan secara demokratis. Dalam penyelenggaraan kekuasaan yang demokratis itu telah diatur pula distribusi kekuasaan termasuk pembatasan dan pengawasan demi mencegah penyalahgunaan kekuasaan.

6. APAKAH GEREJA ITU?
6.1. Pengertian etimologis

Kata gereja berasal dari bahasa Portugis igreja yang sepadan dengan bahasa Perancis eglise, bahasa Spanyol iglesia, dan bahasa Latin ecclesia, yang kesemuanya bersumber dari bahasa Yunani ekklesia. Dalam bahasa Yunani klasik, ekklesia berarti kumpulan atau pertemuan. Sejak Solon (639-559 SM), yang dikenal sebagai pelopor demokrasi Yunani dan sebagai salah satu dari ketujuh orang bijaksana yang amat termasyhur, menyusun hukum yang baru di Athena, istilah ekklesia digunakan dengan arti sidang umum. Dan sejak Cleisthenes mengubah Athena menjadi negara yang benar-benar demokratis, ekklesia (sidang umum) menjadi lembaga tertinggi negara.
Lima abad kemudian, orang-orang kristen memilih kata ekklesia untuk menerjemahkan istilah Iberani qahal yang berarti suatu umat yang dipanggil untuk berkumpul bersama/bersekutu. Jadi secara etimologis, ekklesia adalah suatu sidang atau umat yang berkumpul/bersekutu karena ada panggilan untuk bersidang, berkumpul/bersekutu.
Bahasa-bahasa Eropa Utara menggunakan istilah lain untuk kata gereja, seperti: church (Inggeris), kirche (Jerman), dan kerk (Belanda). Kata-kata itu berasal dari kata Yunani kurion, atau kuriakon yang berarti kepunyaan/milik Tuhan.
Dari penggunaan kata-kata ekklesia dan kuriakon, dapatlah dikatakan bahwa Gereja adalah sidang atau persekutuan dari orang-orang milik Tuhan.

6.2. Hakikat Gereja
Apakah sebenarnya gereja itu? Pengertian etimologis tersebut di atas menunjukkan bahwa gereja bukanlah gedung (benda mati), melainkan persekutuan dari manusia yang menyadari bahwa mereka adalah milik Tuhan. Persekutuan itu terdiri dari orang-orang yang dipanggil dan dipilih menjadi umat Allah.[23] Dengan demikian, Gereja adalah komunitas dari umat Allah.[24]
Komunitas umat Allah ini in concreto terlihat lewat organisasi gerejawi, jabatan-jabatan, tata dasar, tata gereja, gedung ibadah, liturgi, pemberitaan Firman Allah, pelayanan sakramen, dan sebagainya. Tetapi komunitas umat Allah yang disebut gereja itu lebih dari pada apa yang dapat diamati. Sesungguhnya di Alkitab terdapat banyak gambaran mengenai gereja, namun untuk saat ini cukup dua gambaran saja yang akan kita bicarakan, yaitu gereja selaku mempelai Kristus dan gereja selaku tubuh Kristus.
Hubungan antara mempelai pria dan mempelai wanita menunjukkan adanya suatu relasi yang amat dalam dan khusus. Pertama-tama perlu ditekankan bahwa relasi itu di dasarkan pada cinta kasih yang tulus. Dalam hal itu, cinta kasih Kristus tidak dapat diragukan lagi. Namun bagaimana dengan cinta kasih gereja selaku mempelai wanita? Cinta kasih yang tulus telah ditunjukkan oleh Kristus lewat kesediaanNya untuk mengorbankan diri demi keselamatan mempelai wanitanya. Ia memberi diri demi yang dikasihiNya. Kedua, mempelai pria dan mempelai wanita merupakan partner hidup. Segala persoalan hidup dihadapi bersama. Mereka merupakan partner kerja, partner dalam membagi suka dan duka, bahkan partner dalam segala-galanya. Ketiga, seperti yang terdapat di dalam Kidung Agung 2:16, "Kekasihku kepunyaanku, dan aku kepunyaan dia...," demikian pula gereja perlu menyadari bahwa ia adalah milik Kristus. Dalam hal itu terkandung pengertian bahwa kendatipun Kristus telah mengorbankan diri baginya, namun dapat saja ia memilih untuk menjadi milik dari yang lain, namun ia tidak sudi berbuat demikian dan ia memilih Kristus untuk memiliki dirinya.
Menurut Alkitab, gereja adalah Tubuh Kristus dan Kristus adalah kepalanya (Efesus 1:22; 5:23 dan Kolose 1:18). Gereja selaku Tubuh Kristus adalah suatu organisme spiritual. Kepala dan anggota-anggota tubuh dihubungkan satu dengan lainnya secara spiritual. Untuk hidup, tubuh membutuhkan kepala dan kepala membutuhkan tubuh dan agar keseluruhannya dapat berfungsi sebagaimana mestinya maka anggota-anggota tubuh pun harus lengkap, dan fungsi mereka adalah untuk saling melengkapi satu sama lainnya. Lukisan tentang hubungan kepala dan tubuh itu menunjukkan bahwa gereja adalah suatu organisme yang hidup.[25] Sebagai satu organisme yang hidup, maka gereja selaku Tubuh Kristus yang berada di dunia ini, tidak dapat dibatasi oleh suatu tempat, bangsa atau negara tertentu. Gereja yang hadir di suatu tempat atau di suatu negara tertentu bukanlah cabang dari suatu organisasi gerejawi yang berada di suatu negara adikuasa di Eropa, Amerika atau di mana saja; melainkan bagian integral dari organisme tubuh yang kepalanya adalah Yesus Kristus. Oleh karena itu, secara eklesiologis, dapatlah dikatakan bahwa segala upaya "kontekstualisasi" teologi yang bertolak dari prasangka buruk terhadap teologi Barat yang diwarnai oleh sentimen politis yang dilandaskan pada semangat regionalisme ekstrim, tidak lebih daripada suatu usaha untuk merobek-robek Tubuh Kristus selaku satu organisme yang hidup.

7. APAKAH TUJUAN GEREJA?
Gereja ada bukan untuk sekedar eksis. Ia memiliki tujuan yang hendak dicapai. Karena ia memiliki tujuan maka ia pun memiliki misi demi mencapai tujuan itu. Apakah yang menjadi tujuan gereja di dunia ini?
Alkitab Perjanjian Lama dan Perjanjian Baru menyaksikan bahwa Allah berkehendak untuk menyelamatkan dan memulihkan manusia, bahkan seluruh ciptaanNya, dari kondisi yang sangat memprihatinkan. Untuk itu Allah mengutus PutraNya, Yesus Kristus sebagai pelaksana yang sempurna dari kehendakNya. Tujuan kedatangan Yesus Kristus ke dunia ini ialah untuk melaksanakan kehendak BapaNya. Ia menyampaikan kabar baik dari Allah lewat pemberitaan dan perbuatan. Yesus Kristus Juru Selamat itulah pula yang telah mendirikan gereja di atas dasar pengakuan iman bahwa Yesus adalah Mesias, Anak Allah yang hidup (Matius 16:15-18). Karena Yesus Kristus yang mendirikan gereja, maka dapatlah dikatakan bahwa gereja ada oleh dan untuk Kristus. Oleh karena itu tujuan dan misi Kristus di dunia ini adalah juga tujuan dan misi gereja itu sendiri. Sebagaimana Yesus Kristus menyadari bahwa tujuan kedatanganNya ke dunia ini adalah untuk memberlakukan kehendak Allah, maka demikian pula gereja harus menyadari bahwa tujuan keberadaannya di dunia ini adalah juga untuk memberlakukan kehendak Allah. Dan sebagaimana Kristus telah melaksanakan misinya untuk menyampaikan kabar baik lewat pemberitaan dan perbuatan, maka gereja pun wajib melaksanakan tugas panggilan atau misinya untuk menyampaikan kabar baik lewat pemberitaan dan perbuatan. Tentu saja kita tidak dapat menduplikasi perbuatan Kristus yang mengorbankan diri di atas kayu salib, namun tindakan kita perlu diwarnai semangat pengorbanan sang Kepala Gereja itu! Jadi jelas bahwa tujuan ultim gereja di dunia ini adalah memberlakukan kehendak Allah, sehingga doa yang senantiasa kita ucapkan, "... datanglah KerajaanMu, jadilah kehendakMu di bumi seperti di sorga..." (Matius 6:10), benar-benar dapat diwujudnyatakan.
Menyadari akan tujuan keberadaan dan tugas panggilan (misi) gereja di dunia ini, maka Gereja-gereja di Indonesia dengan yakin mengatakan bahwa:
Gereja-gereja di Indonesia telah ditempatkan oleh Tuhan sendiri untuk melaksanakan tugas panggilannya dan menjadi berkat bagi semua orang di dalam negara Pancasila yang sedang menjalankan pembangunan nasional sebagai pengamalan Pancasila menuju era tinggal landas menjelang akhir abad ke-20.
Melaksanakan tugas panggilan itu tidak lain berarti melaksanakan kehendak Tuhan yang tidak berubah (bnd. Ibr 13:8) di tengah-tengah kehidupan bangsa-bangsa dan masyarakat dunia yang terus-menerus berubah. Oleh karena itu, gereja-gereja di Indonesia terus-menerus bergumul memahami kehendak Tuhan itu dari waktu ke waktu.[26]

8. FUNGSI GEREJA
Secara tradisional, ada dua pemahaman tentang fungsi gereja dalam eklesiologi. Pertama, mereka yang memandang gereja sebagai agen keselamatan, dan kedua, mereka yang memandang gereja selaku komunitas eklusif dari orang-orang kudus.[27] Pada Konferensi Edinburgh tentang Iman dan Tata Tertib (tahun 1937), dikatakan bahwa fungsi gereja ialah untuk memuliakan Tuhan lewat penyembahan dan pelayanan pengurbanan serta menjadi utusan Allah di dunia ini. Itu berarti bahwa gereja memiliki fungsi yang rangkap tiga:
1 memuliakan Tuhan lewat penyembahan (adoration)
2 memuliakan Tuhan lewat pelayanan pengorbanan (sacrificial service)
3 memuliakan Tuhan lewat menjadi utusan Allah di dunia ini (to be God's missionary to the world).
Menyembah Tuhan berarti mengakui kedaulatan Tuhan dalam kehidupan hic et nunc. Mengakui kedaulatan Tuhan harus tampak lewat kata, sikap dan tindak yang senantiasa menempatkan Tuhan selaku yang disembah dan bukan berusaha untuk menempatkan diri sendiri sebagai yang disembah.
Gereja tidak eksis untuk diri sendiri. Gereja ada di dunia ini demi dan untuk dunia ini. Oleh karena itu gereja tidak boleh terarah kepada diri sendiri melainkan harus senantiasa terarah keluar. Gereja tidak boleh terpukau dengan keberadaan diri sendiri lalu melupakan fungsinya yang utama. Gereja tidak boleh membangun "menara Babel" bagi kemuliaan diri melainkan terus-menerus hidup dalam kepedulian kepada yang lain, sebagaimana Allah sendiri memperdulikan kita.
Menjadi utusan Allah di dunia ini berarti gereja diangkat oleh Allah sendiri untuk menjadi duta kebenaran, kebaikan dan keadilan yang bukan hanya disampaikan lewat mulut, tetapi harus nyata lewat kata dan perbuatan. Benarkah Gereja masih berfungsi selaku duta kebenaran, kebaikan dan keadilan?

9. KEKUASAAN GEREJA
Sejarah gereja menyaksikan bahwa dari abad ke abad dan hingga pada saat ini dan bahkan untuk seterusnya gereja ada dan akan terus berada oleh karena ia memiliki kekuasaan yang "luar biasa". Apakah sumber kekuasaan gereja? Dan untuk apakah gereja memperoleh kekuasaan itu?
Mengenai sumber kekuasaan gereja, Berkhof mengatakan bahwa "Yesus Kristus bukan hanya mendirikan Gereja, melainkan juga mengaruniakannya kekuasaan atau otoritas yang dibutuhkannya."[28] Itu berarti bahwa Yesus Kristus adalah sumber kekuasaan gereja. Pencurahan kuasa Roh Kudus yang diceriterakan di Kisah Rasul-Rasul menunjukkan bahwa sejak saat itu Allah telah melimpahkan wewenang dan kekuasaan kepada gerejaNya.[29]
Untuk apakah Allah melimpahkan wewenang dan kekuasaan kepada gereja? Jawabannya ialah agar gereja dapat berperan serta dalam rencana penyelamatan yang dilakukan Allah dan agar gereja dapat mencapai tujuannya untuk memberlakukan kehendak Allah di dunia ini, dan agar gereja dapat pula melaksanakan tugas panggilannya. Itu berarti bahwa kekuasaan gereja adalah kekuasaan yang dikaruniakan Allah untuk melayani. Karena kekuasaan gereja adalah karunia Allah, maka kekuasaan gereja bukanlah kekuasaan yang independen.[30] Oleh karena itu penyelenggaraan kekuasaan gereja haruslah dilakukan sesuai dengan kehendak si pemberi kekuasaan itu sendiri.

10. HUBUNGAN GEREJA DAN NEGARA
Gereja dan negara berada di dunia yang sama. Tidak seorang pun warga gereja yang tidak menjadi warga dari sesuatu negara. Oleh karena itu mau atau tidak, gereja dan negara pasti memiliki hubungan. Bagaimanakah gerangan jenis hubungan yang terdapat antara gereja dan negara itu?
Menurut Kranenburg, "hubungan antara negara dan gereja telah menimbulkan kesukaran-kesukaran besar dalam pelbagai bentuk untuk teori dan praktek."[31] Kenyataannya, baik negara maupun gereja, kedua-duanya merupakan "bentuk-bentuk golongan, tatanan-tatanan kerukunan, yakni organisasi-organisasi sesama manusia terdiri dari orang-orang yang itu-itu juga."[32] Sebagaimana yang telah disebutkan sebelumnya, baik gereja maupun negara, kedua-duanya memiliki kekuasaan yang amat besar. Kedua-duanya memiliki perangkat pemerintahan, kedua-duanya memiliki norma-norma dan peraturan-peraturan. Oleh karena itu, bukan tidak mungkin terjadi konflik antara keduanya.
Sejarah menunjukkan bahwa hubungan antara gereja dan negara memang tidak selamanya harmonis. Tidak selamanya serasi dan selaras! Bahkan sejak kelahirannya, gereja telah disambut dengan penuh kecurigaan oleh masyarakat sekitar dan pemerintah (negara) yang berkuasa pada waktu itu. Penghambatan dan penganiayaan pertama dari pihak negara terjadi pada tahun 64, di kota Roma atas perintah kaisar Nero. Hal itu diceriterakan secara lengkap oleh Tacitus, sejarawan Roma yang cukup terkenal.[33] Penghambatan dan penganiayaan terhadap gereja berlangsung terus sampai tahun 313. Selama penghambatan dan penganiayaan itu, Gereja tidak pernah mengambil sikap bermusuhan terhadap negara. Gereja tetap setia mengikuti ajaran Yesus dan nasihat Paulus untuk menghormati pemerintah, mengerjakan kewajiban selaku warga negara yang baik, bahkan menaikkan doa syafaat bagi pemerintah. Bentuk tertua dari doa syafaat yang tercatat dalam sejarah terdapat di dalam I Clement, sebagai berikut:
Grant that we may be obedient to... our rulers and governors upon the earth.... Thou, Master, hast given the power of sovereignty to them.... And to them, Lord, grant health, peace, concord, firmness that they may administer the government which thou hast given them without offense.[34]
Pada tahun 313, Kaisar Konstantinus Agung mengeluarkan sebuah keputusan yang menyatakan bahwa gereja memperoleh kebebasan penuh. Keputusan itu dikenal dengan nama edik Milano. Selain kebebasan penuh, gereja memperoleh kembali seluruh harta milik yang telah dirampas Negara. Dengan demikian gereja telah memasuki babak baru dengan tantangan yang baru. Pada tahun 380, Kaisar Theodosius mengeluarkan suatu keputusan yang mewajibkan seluruh rakyat untuk menganut agama kristen. Gereja diresmikan menjadi gereja negara.Dari satu sisi, status baru ini memang menguntungkan gereja karena keanggotaan gereja secara kuantitas meningkat. Gereja pun dapat menanamkan nilai-nilai dan cita-cita kristiani ke dalam kehidupan masyarakat bangsa Romawi. Hal itu tentu saja didukung oleh kaisar, karena nilai-nilai cinta kasih, kepatuhan, saling menghormati, kesederhanaan hidup dan sebagainya sangat diperlukan oleh negara demi menjaga keutuhan dan kesatuan. Namun karena gereja baru pertama kali memperoleh kebebasan dan dukungan negara, gereja belum mengetahui adanya bahaya caesaropapisme yaitu kecenderungan sang kaisar untuk memandang dirinya sebagai kepala gereja. Kendatipun ia tidak menyamakan diri dengan Allah, tetapi jika kita mengamati dengan cermat mozaik Kaisar Justinianus dalam gereja di San Vitale, Ravenna (berasal dari abad VI), maka kita akan memperoleh kesan bahwa jika ia bukan seorang dewa, ia pun bukan manusia biasa. Hal itu menunjukkan betapa besarnya kekuasaan kaisar di dalam gereja. Sadar atau tidak, gereja telah menjadi alat dan hamba yang harus mengabdi kepada negara. Hal itulah pula yang ditempuh oleh Gereja Ortodoks-Timur (Gereja Katolik Yunani) yang berada di wilayah kekaisaran Romawi Timur dengan ibu kotanya Constantinopel (Byzantium). Bagi Gereja Ortodoks-Timur, kaisar dipandang sebagai wakil Allah di dunia ini.
Gereja Romawi-Barat berpendapat bahwa negara dapat pula disusupi oleh unsur-unsur satanik dan oleh sebab itu perlu diwaspadai. Sikap yang demikian itu pertama-tama ditunjukkan oleh Uskup Ambrosius dari kota Milano. Pada suatu hari di tahun 390, kaisar Theodosius Agung menjadi sangat murka karena seorang panglimanya terbunuh mati dalam suatu huru-hara di kota Tesalonika. Theodosius segera mengirimkan pasukannya ke kota itu dan membunuh sekitar 7000 orang secara membabi-buta. Uskup Ambrosius tidak menyetujui tindakan kaisar, oleh karena itu ia tidak memperkenankan kaisar mengikuti Perjamuan Kudus, sampai kaisar mengaku dan menyesali dosanya di hadapan umum. Kaisar Theodosius memang membuat penitensia di hadapan umum sebagai tanda penyesalan terhadap dosa yang telah diperbuatnya.
Bagi Uskup Ambrosius, kaisar memang termasuk di dalam gereja, namun ia tidak boleh menguasai gereja. Ambrosius menyadari betapa dahsyatnya bahaya caesaropapisme itu. Tetapi Ambrosius melangkah lebih jauh lagi dan membuka suatu peluang bagi bahaya yang lain. Konon, pada suatu hari, orang-orang kristen membakar sebuah sinagoge Yahudi dan sebuah tempat ibadah kaum bidat. Kaisar Theodosius hendak menghukum para pelaku pembakaran itu, tetapi Ambrosius menuntut agar mereka diampuni. Theodosius tunduk kepada keinginan Ambrosius, dan hal itu merupakan benih bagi papocaesarisme, yaitu kecenderungan pimpinan gereja untuk merasa lebih berkuasa dari kaisar, karena merasa bahwa ia adalah wakil Kristus di dunia ini. Dengan demikian terlihat pula bahwa unsur-unsur satanik bukan hanya dapat menyusup masuk kedalam kekuasaan negara tetapi juga dapat menyusup masuk kedalam kekuasaan gereja.
Augustinus (354-430) berhasil merakit filsafat politik pertama yang memberi landasan yang rasional bagi teori teokratis.[35] Menurut Augustinus,
... ada dua macam negara. Yang pertama adalah Negara Allah (civitas Dei) yang sering juga disebutnya sebagai negara surgawi. Yang kedua ialah negara sekuler (civitas terrena/negara duniawi) yang sering juga disebutnya sebagai negara diaboli. Negara yang paling baik dan oleh sebab itu harus senantiasa diupayakan perwujudannya ialah negara Allah. Negara sekuler adalah negara yang buruk dan oleh sebab itu tak layak menjadi dambaan manusia.
Kehidupan di dalam negara Allah diwarnai oleh iman, ketaatan dan kasih Allah. Negara Allah menghargai segala sesuatu yang baik seperti: kejujuran, keadilan, keluhuran budi, kesetiaan, moralitas yang terpuji, keindahan dan lain-lain sebagainya. Negara sekuler diwarnai oleh dosa, keangkuhan dan cinta egois. Negara sekuler merupakan manifestasi dari ketidakjujuran, pengumbaran hawa nafsu, ketidakadilan, pengkhianatan, kebobrokan moral, keburukan, kemaksiatan, kejahatan dan lain-lain sebagainya.[36]
Dari pandangan Augustinus tersebut tadi, jelas terlihat bahwa ia telah mengubah negara ideal Plato menjadi civitas Dei, sehingga idealisme Plato telah menjadi idealisme kristen.
Ajaran Augustinus sering disalahpahami dengan menafsirkan civitas Dei sebagai gereja, sedangkan civitas terrena ialah negara. Dengan mengatakan bahwa civitas terrena hanya berguna jika ia melayani civitas Dei, maka Paus-Paus di abad pertengahan menggunakan pandangan Augustinus itu untuk menempatkan diri di atas kaisar dan memerintah serta mengatur negara.
Demikianlah gambaran hubungan yang disharmonis, bahkan yang seringkali penuh dengan ketegangan antara gereja dan negara yang acap kali terjadi di sepanjang sejarah.

11. BEBERAPA SOLUSI YANG DITAWARKAN
Martin Luther (1483-1546) menolak doktrin papal mengenai teori dua pedang yang mengklaim segala kekuasaan di dunia ini, baik kekuasaan temporal (dalam negara) maupun kekuasaan spiritual (dalam gereja) telah diberikan kepada Paus. Martin Luther mengatakan bahwa para penguasa/pemerintah menerima kekuasaan mereka langsung dari Tuhan.[37] Dengan didasari oleh gagasan Augustinus, Luther mengatakan bahwa ada dua jenis kerajaan yang ada di antara manusia. Yang satu bersifat spiritual dan diperintah oleh Firman tanpa pedang, yang melaluinya manusia dijadikan saleh dan benar demi meraih kehidupan yang kekal. Yang satunya lagi bersifat sementara dan diperintah dengan pedang agar mereka yang tidak menjadi saleh lewat Firman dapat dipaksa berbuat benar demi ketertiban dunia ini.[38] Ia berpendapat bahwa negara adalah institusi ilahi yang hendak mencegah anarki. Oleh karena itu ia memperkenankan campur-tangan negara dalam urusan gereja demi kepentingan gereja itu sendiri.
Yohanes Calvin (1509-1564) menegaskan bahwa gereja dan negara merupakan dua lingkungan yang diperintah oleh satu penguasa, yaitu: Yesus Kristus. Apabila negara/pemerintah memuliakan Tuhan dengan mengupayakan keadilan, perdamaian, dan kebebasan, maka gereja/orang-orang kristen wajib bekerjasama dan mendukungnya. Dukungan dan kerjasama gereja dengan negara terbatas sejauh negara tidak merampas/mengganggu kesetiaan gereja terhadap Yesus Kristus.
Karl Barth (1886-1968) sependapat dengan Reformator Yohanes Calvin, namun ia menambahkan beberapa pokok pikiran sebagai berikut:
1 Negara memperoleh tugas menurut ketetapan Allah di tengah-tengah suatu dunia yang berada dalam genggaman dosa dan dalam dunia yang demikian itu pula gereja berdiri. Negara wajib menjalankan tugasnya itu dengan segala kearifan dan kemampuan untuk menegakkan keadilan dan perdamaian; dan untuk itu ia diberi kekuasaan.
2 Hubungan gereja dan negara merupakan hubungan dari lingkaran-lingkaran konsentris yang berpusatkan Yesus Kristus.
3 Gereja dan negara tidak boleh dibaurkan. Gereja harus membatasi diri sedemikian rupa sehingga ia tidak menjadi negara, dan demikian pula negara tidak boleh menjadi gereja.
4 Gereja tidak boleh menguasai negara dan negara pun tidak boleh menguasai gereja. Namun Gereja berkewajiban untuk memperingatkan negara/pemerintah akan kerajaan/ kekuasaan dan keadilan Allah.
Pada masa kini, teori kedaulatan hukum seolah-olah memberikan harapan penyelesaian yang memuaskan. Jika semua pihak tunduk kepada hukum, maka hukum pasti dapat mengatur, membatasi dan mengawasi penggunaan kekuasaan oleh semua pihak. Dengan demikian segala bentuk konflik pun dapat dicegah.

12. BEBERAPA CATATAN AKHIR
1 Hingga kini belum ditemukan suatu solusi yang paling tepat dan paling memuaskan tentang hubungan gereja dan negara itu.
2 Sangat sulit untuk mengatur dan memisahkan kewenangan dan otonomi negara dari kewenangan dan otonomi gereja. Karena tidak dapat dikatakan bahwa negara hanya mengatur kehidupan duniawi dan gereja mengatur kehidupan spiritual. Bukankah yang "duniawi" itu selalu memiliki aspek spiritual dan demikian pula sebaliknya? Demikian pula sangat sulit untuk mengatakan bahwa dalam kondisi yang "begini" atau dalam kondisi yang "begitu" negara boleh "campur tangan" dalam "wilayah kekuasaan gereja."
3 Jika kita mengangkat hukum sebagai kekuasaan tertinggi, sehingga negara dan gereja tunduk kepadanya, sesungguh-nya ada bahaya lain yang sedang mengancam. Hukum yang seharusnya melayani kepentingan manusia akan menjadi dewa baru, sehingga manusialah yang mengabdi kepada hukum.
4 Sebaiknya kita menghayati dan mengamalkan motto: Biarkanlah negara menjadi negara dan gereja menjadi gereja. Maksudnya ialah negara akan benar-benar menjadi negara jika ia sungguh-sungguh memahami apa tujuan, tugas panggilan dan fungsi negara serta mengetahui asal kekuasaan yang dimilikinya, sehingga kekuasaan itu akan digunakan dengan sebaik-baiknya dan dengan penuh tanggung jawab, sesuai dengan tujuan, tugas panggilan dan fungsinya itu. Demikian pula gereja akan benar-benar menjadi gereja, apabila ia sungguh-sungguh memahami apa tujuan, tugas panggilan dan fungsi gereja serta siapa yang mengaruniakan kekuasaannya, sehingga ia tidak akan menyalahgunakan kekuasaan yang dimilikinya itu, melainkan akan digunakan dengan sebaik-baiknya, sesuai dengan kehendak dari Dia yang mengaruniakan kekuasaan itu demi mencapai tujuan, dan demi melaksanakan tugas panggilan dan fungsinya. Baik negara, maupun gereja, harus tetap mewaspadai akan upaya penyusupan unsur-unsur satanik yang hendak melumpuhkan dan menghancurkan eksistensinya. Jika gereja dan negara dapat mengamalkan pemahaman yang demikian itu, tentu tidak akan timbul masalah apapun juga. Namun karena gereja dan negara yang ada di dunia ini tidak sempurna, maka pengamalan dari pemahaman ideal itu pun tidak akan pernah sempurna, sehingga masalah pasti akan tetap ada. Namun yang penting ialah bagaimana meminimalkan permasalahan itu sehingga permasalahan itu tidak lagi menjadi ancaman bagi relasi antara gereja dan negara, melainkan menjadi daya pendorong yang memacu langkah maju bersama dalam suatu bentuk hubungan yang komplementaris dan dinamis.


Catatan:

[1] Lihat, R.F.Beerling, Filsafat Dewasa Ini (Jakarta: P.N.Balai Pustaka, 1966), hlm.8-9.
[2] Ibid., hlm. 9.
[3] aletheia atau kebenaran sebenarnya berarti sesuatu yang sudah jelas, yang tak tersembunyi atau yang tidak tertutup.
[4] problemma menempatkan sesuatu di depan atau di luar dirinya (agar dapat diamati/diteliti!).
[5] Lihat, J.H.Rapar, Filsafat Politik Plato, cet. 2 (Jakarta: Rajawali Pers, 1991), hlm. 63.
[6] Aristoteles, The Politics, 1252aI.
[7] Lihat, J.H. Rapar, Filsafat Politik Aristoteles (Jakarta: Rajawali Pers, 1988), hlm. 33.
[8] Lihat John Locke Two Treatises of Government (1690), dan band. John Locke, "Concerning Civil Government," Great Books of The Western World (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, inc. 1952), pp. 46-54.
[9] Lihat Lowell Bair, trans., The Essential Rousseau (New York: New American Library, 1974), p. 17.
[10] J.H.Rapar, Filsafat Politik Machiavelli (Jakarta: Rajawali Pers, 1990), hlm. 39.
[11] Lihat Aristotle, Politics 1.1 - 1.2
[12] John Locke, "Two Treatises of Government", Great Political Thinkers: Plato to the Present, William Ebenstein (New Delhi: Oxford & IBH Publishing CO., 1969), pp. 405-406.
[13] Lihat G.A.Jacobsen and M.H.Lipman, Political Science (New York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1979), pp. 17-18.
[14] Lihat Jan Hendrik Rapar, "The View of Man In The Philosophy of Pancasila: An Attempt at a New Understanding" (Ph.D. diss., The US International University, 1985), p. 56.
[15] Tiga Undang-Undang Dasar: UUD RI 1945, Kontstitusi RIS, UUD Sementara RI (Jakarta: Ghalia Indonesia, 1977), hlm. 7.
[16] Jacobsen, op. cit., hlm. 21.
[17] The Politics, 1253a1 f.
[18] Ibid.
[19] Lihat Jacobsen, op. cit., hlm. 28.
[20] Lihat Mac Iver, Negara Moderen, terj. Moertono (Jakarta: Aksara Baru, 1984), hlm. 172-173.
[21] Rapar, Filsafat Politik Plato, hlm.95-98.
[22] Rapar, Filsafat Politik Aristoteles, hlm. 57-61.
[23] Lihat Jan Hendrik Rapar, "The Ekklesia of God" (Th.D. diss., International Seminary, 1982), p. 7.
[24] Ibid., p. 17.
[25] Rapar, The Ekklesia, p. 25.
[26] Persekutuan Gereja-Gereja di Indonesia, Dalam Kemantapan Kebersamaan Menapaki Dekade Penuh Harapan (Jakarta: PT BPK Gunung Mulia, 1990), hlm. 43.
[27] Rapar, The Ekklesia, p. 60.
[28] Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Grand Rapids: Wm.B.Eeerdmans Publishing Co., 1988), p. 593.
[29] Band. Joseph M. Gettys, What Presbyterians Believe (Clinton, n.p., 1968), p. 89.
[30] Band. Berkhof, Ibid., p. 594.
[31] R. Kranenburg, Ilmu negara Umum, terj. Tk. B. Sabaroedin (Jakarta: Pradnya Paramita, 1982), hlm. 245.
[32] Ibid.
[33] Clarence Tucker Craig, The Beginning of Christianity (New York: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, MCMXLIII), p. 316.
[34] Ibid., p. 320.
[35] J.H.Rapar, Filsafat Politik Augustinus (Jakarta: Rajawali Pers, 1989), hlm. 30-31.
[36] Ibid., hlm. 59.
[37] David Thomson, ed., Political Ideas (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1982), p. 36.
[38] Ibid., pp. 41-42.